Subjective Skewness of Return as an Explanation of the Optimal Choice between Gambles in Cumulative Prospect Theory

Main Article Content

David Peel

Abstract

Given that the expected return and variance of return of two gambles are equal  the hypothesis that the gamble with the greater  positive skewness of return will be chosen by an expected utility maximiser is appealing. However the hypothesis is  not, in general, correct. Brockett and Garven (1998) and Brocket and Kahane (1992) demonstrate this both theoretically and by constructing counter examples.A particularly revealing example is the following one constructed by Brockett and Kahane.  Gamble A has the two outcomes 2.45 and 7.49 with probabilities 0.5141 and 0.4859 respectively. Gamble B has the three outcomes 0, 4.947 and 10 with probabilities 0.12096, 0.750085 and 0.128955 respectively. Even though gamble A exhibits  lower expected return,  a higher variance and lower  positive skewness than gamble B it is preferred to gamble B by an expected utility maximiser on the basis of any standard utility function  such as power, log or exponential.  Consequently in this  example of theirs the expected utility maximiser exhibits an aversion to higher expected return and higher skewness and a preference for higher variance. As noted by Brockett and Kahane these results cannot be dismissed as decision makers “trading” variance for mean or skewness or having a strange idiosyncratic utility function.

Article Details

Section
Articles

References

Allais, Maurice.1953. “Le Comportement de l’Homme Rationnel devant le Risque: Critique des Postulats et Axiomes de l’Ecole Américaine,” Econometrica 21, 503–546.

M. Allais and O. Hagen (1979), editors, Expected Utility Hypotheses and the Allais Paradox. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

Ali, M. (1977): Probability and utility estimates for racetrack bettors, in: Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 85, pp. 803-815.

Barberis, N. and Huang, M. (2005) “Stocks as Lotteries: The Implications of Probability Weighting for Security Prices” Yale University and Stanford / Cheung Kong GSB

Brockett, P.L. and Kahane, Y. (1992) “Risk, Return, Skewness and Preference”. Management Science, 38, 851-866.

Brockett,P.L. and Garven, J.R. (1998) “ A Reexamination of the Relationship between Preference and Moment Orderings by Rational Risk Averse Investors ” Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance Theory, 23,pp127-137.

Cain, M. and Peel, D. A. (2004) “Utility and Skewness of Return in Gambling”, Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance Theory, 29, pp145-163.

Friedman, M. and Savage, L.J. (1948) "The Utility Analysis of Choices Involving Risk," Journal of Political Economy, LVI, 279-304. ...

Golec, J. and M. Tamarkin, M. (1998),” Bettors Love Skewness, Not Risk, at the Horse Track”., Journal of Political Economy 106, 205-225.

Kahneman, D. and Tversky, A. (1979), “Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision under Risk,” Econometrica, 2, 263-91.

Law, D and Peel, D.A. (2007) “Skewness as an explanation of gambling in cumulative prospect theory”. Applied Economics

Markowitz, Harry, M. 1952 “The Utility of Wealth”, Journal of Political Economy, 56, 151-154.

Peel, D and Law, D. (2007) “Betting on odds on Favorites as an Optimal Choice in Cumulative Prospect Theory," Economics Bulletin, vol. 4(26), pages 1-10.

Samuelson, P.A. (1963), "Risk and Uncertainty: A Fallacy of Large Numbers", Scientia, 153-158.

Tversky, A. and Kahneman, D. (1992), “Advances in Prospect Theory: Cumulative Representation of Uncertainty,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5:4, 297-323.

Taleb, N.N. (2004)"Bleed or Blowup: What Does Empirical Psychology Tell US About the Preference For Negative Skewness? ", Journal of Behavioral Finance, 5, 2-7.

Tversky, A., and D. Kahneman (1992), “Advances in Prospect Theory: Cumulative Representation of Uncertainty,” Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 5, 297-323.